Steven G
Elite Member
- Joined
- Dec 30, 2014
- Messages
- 14,591
Hi,
I did a proof that my mathematician friend said was wrong. He claims that I should show bijections. I am sure that he is correct but I do not see why my trivial proof is wrong.
The statement of the theorem along with my proof is below.
Theorem 2: Let U be some universal set. Define a relation on P(U) by A∼B iff A and B have the same cardinality; that is, iff there is a bijection f:A→B. Then ∼ is an equivalence relation on P(U).
Proof:
Reflexive: A∼A since A and A have the same cardinality.
Symmetric: Suppose A∼B. Then A and B have the same cardinality, so B and A have the same cardinality. Then B∼A.
Transitive: Suppose A∼B and B∼C. Then A and B have the same cardinality, and B and C have the same cardinality. Since a set has only one cardinality, it follows that A and C must have the same cardinality, and A∼C.
Since the relation ∼ is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive, it is an equivalence relation.
Thanks for your time!
I did a proof that my mathematician friend said was wrong. He claims that I should show bijections. I am sure that he is correct but I do not see why my trivial proof is wrong.
The statement of the theorem along with my proof is below.
Theorem 2: Let U be some universal set. Define a relation on P(U) by A∼B iff A and B have the same cardinality; that is, iff there is a bijection f:A→B. Then ∼ is an equivalence relation on P(U).
Proof:
Reflexive: A∼A since A and A have the same cardinality.
Symmetric: Suppose A∼B. Then A and B have the same cardinality, so B and A have the same cardinality. Then B∼A.
Transitive: Suppose A∼B and B∼C. Then A and B have the same cardinality, and B and C have the same cardinality. Since a set has only one cardinality, it follows that A and C must have the same cardinality, and A∼C.
Since the relation ∼ is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive, it is an equivalence relation.
Thanks for your time!
Attachments
Last edited by a moderator: