You really cannot deal with infinities as if they were numbers. And dots require a definition, or in many cases a convention we all agree on. I don't understand the sequence of nines in the denominator. If we use the decimal system to represent π then π=3.141592653589793238462…=3+101+1004+10001+100005+1000009+…You cannot even write 3+1000000000…14159265… - at least not if you want to be understood - let alone nines in the denominator. Note that I wrote dots although the numerator is a sequence of changing digits and the denominator is a regular sequence that only adds a zero from term to term.
Dots are always dependent on their context. That's why you cannot take 0.999…=1, rip off the context and replace ones by dot nines. If you want to write unusual dots in π, I suggest
Infinity is a symbol you should try to avoid. It makes sense in sums k=0∑∞ak:=n→∞limk=0∑nak as an abbreviation and sometimes as the result of a limit like limn→∞n=∞, but even that is already an abbreviation for a complex logical statement, not something infinitely large. It is rather something growing beyond all finite bounds!
As you so correctly pointed to and I must admit, 0.14159...=1000...14159... is not something I've seen in my mathematical life. Although 0.14159... has an infinite repetend, it's actually a finite number, sits somewhere between 0.14 and 0.15 and the trailing dots simply imply, in the Pythagorean sense, incommensurability. What is incommensurability?
As you so correctly pointed to and I must admit, 0.14159...=1000...14159... is not something I've seen in my mathematical life. Although 0.14159... has an infinite repetend, it's actually a finite number, sits somewhere between 0.14 and 0.15 and the trailing dots simply imply, in the Pythagorean sense, incommensurability. What is incommensurability?
Yes, that's another issue. The digits depend on the number system that we use. Ok, π is unpredictable in every system, but 1/7=0.142857 looks a bit different if we use 7 as a base, 1/7=0.1.
The ancient Greeks are again another topic. AFAIK they only knew rational and irrational numbers that could be easily constructed as a length on a straight, and numbers they could not construct like π,32 or certain angles. They knew the difference between the rational side length 2 and the irrational length of the diagonal 8 but had no idea about the properties of π although Archimedes already had quite a good approximation. "Length on a straight" for them was always a ratio, a part of the yardstick: x:y.
It took more than 2,000 years to answer their questions finally. The words we still use: rational, irrational, transcendent were born in their geometric understanding of mathematics. Pythagoras, however, was a charlatan, in my opinion, a numerologist.
Yes, that's another issue. The digits depend on the number system that we use. Ok, π is unpredictable in every system, but 1/7=0.142857 looks a bit different if we use 7 as a base, 1/7=0.1.
The ancient Greeks are again another topic. AFAIK they only knew rational and irrational numbers that could be easily constructed as a length on a straight, and numbers they could not construct like π,32 or certain angles. They knew the difference between the rational side length 2 and the irrational length of the diagonal 8 but had no idea about the properties of π although Archimedes already had quite a good approximation. "Length on a straight" for them was always a ratio, a part of the yardstick: x:y.
It took more than 2,000 years to answer their questions finally. The words we still use: rational, irrational, transcendent were born in their geometric understanding of mathematics. Pythagoras, however, was a charlatan, in my opinion, a numerologist.
Per the linked article on commensurability, incommensurability(a, b) = the nonexistence of a real c, and integers m, n such that mc = a and nc = b i.e. a/b is irrational. If mc = a and nc = b then c = a/m = b/n, which means a = (m/n)b. So if m/n = 2/3, we know we can "commensure" a by breaking b into thirds, and taking two of these pieces. It would be exact.
For irrationals, there is no c and no m and no n that meets this condition. We can approximate though (like we do with π), but <insert appropriate description>.
Well, I didn't know him personally, but by all you can hear about him, he was one. I wouldn't put his name in the same sentence with the giants Euclid and Archimedes, or even folks like Thales, Eratosthenes, or Diophant. I even wouldn't call this famous theorem by his name, only because he knew that 9+16=25. I would call it Law of Cosines! Even Pythagorean triples, e.g. (12709,13500,18541), have been found on Babylonian clay tables about 1829 - 1530 BC, more than 1000 years before he lived!
This site uses cookies to help personalise content, tailor your experience and to keep you logged in if you register.
By continuing to use this site, you are consenting to our use of cookies.